This article argues that the right to have rights, as launched by Hannah Arendt, is relative to refugee displacement and hence translates as a right to asylum. It takes issue with the dominant view that the public/private divide is the locus classicus of the meaning of this primordial right. A different direction of thought is proposed, proceeding from Arendt’s recovery of the spatiality of law. The unencompassibility of place in matters of rights, freedom and equality brings this right into view as a claim at the behest of those who have lost a legal place of their own. This also helps us to gain better understanding of Arendt’s rebuttal of the sharp-edged distinction between refugees and stateless persons and to discover the defiant potential of the right to have rights to illuminate the refugee’s claim to asylum as a claim to an own place where protection can be enjoyed again. |
Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy
About this journalSubscribe to the email alerts for this journal here to receive notifications when a new issue is at your disposal.
Discussion |
Citizens (Even) in Prison |
Authors | Antony Duff |
Author's information |
Article |
The Right to Have Rights as the Right to Asylum |
Keywords | Arendt, asylum, refugeeship, right to have rights, statelessness de facto and de jure |
Authors | Nanda Oudejans |
AbstractAuthor's information |
Article |
Wat is juridisch interactionisme? |
Keywords | interactionism, Lon Fuller, interactional law, legal pluralism, concept of law |
Authors | Wibren van der Burg |
AbstractAuthor's information |
Two phenomena that challenge theories of law in the beginning of the twenty-first century are the regulatory explosion and the emergence of horizontal and interactional forms of law. In this paper, I develop a theory that can address these two phenomena, namely legal interactionism, a theory inspired by the work of Fuller and Selznick. In a pluralist approach, legal interactionism recognizes both interactional law and enacted law, as well as other sources such as contract. We should aim for a pluralistic and gradual concept of law. Because of this pluralist and gradual character, legal interactionism can also do justice to global legal pluralism and to the dynamic intertwinement of health law and bioethics. |
Article |
Racial Profiling and the Presumption of Innocence |
Keywords | racial profiling, stop-and-frisk, presumption of innocence, communicative theories of criminal law, social inequality and criminal law |
Authors | Peter DeAngelis |
AbstractAuthor's information |
I argue that a compelling way to articulate what is wrong with racial profiling in policing is to view racial profiling as a violation of the presumption of innocence. I discuss the communicative nature of the presumption of innocence as an expression of social trust and a protection against the social condemnation of being undeservingly investigated, prosecuted, and convicted for committing a crime. I argue that, given its communicative dimension, failures to extend the presumption of innocence are an expression of disrespect. I take the New York Police Department’s stop-and-frisk policy as an example of racial profiling and argue that its use of race-based forms of suspicion as reasons for making stops is a violation of the presumption of innocence. I maintain that this systemic failure to extend the presumption of innocence to profiled groups reveals the essentially disrespectful nature of the NYPD policy. |
Article |
What Makes Age Discrimination Special? A Philosophical Look at the ECJ Case Law |
Keywords | age discrimination, intergenerational justice, complete-life view, statistical discrimination, anti-discrimination law |
Authors | Axel Gosseries |
AbstractAuthor's information |
This paper provides an account of what makes age discrimination special, going through a set of possible justifications. In the end, it turns out that a full understanding of the specialness of age-based differential treatment requires that we consider together the ‘reliable proxy,’ the ‘complete-life neutrality,’ the ‘sequence efficiency’ and the ‘affirmative egalitarian’ accounts. Depending on the specific age criteria, all four accounts may apply or only some of them. This is the first key message of this paper. The second message of the paper has to do with the age group/birth cohort distinction. All measures that have a differential impact on different cohorts also tend to have a differential impact on various age groups during the transition. The paper points at the practical implications of anti-age-discrimination law for differential treatment between birth cohorts. The whole argument is confronted all along with ECJ cases. |
Book Review |
Nanda Oudejans, Asylum. A Philosophical Inquiry into the International Protection of Refugees |
Authors | Juan M. Amaya-Castro |
Author's information |
Book Review |
B. Sharon Byrd & Joachim Hruschka, Kant’s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary |
Authors | Thomas Mertens |
Author's information |
Book Review |
Mariano Croce & Andrea Salvatore, The Legal Theory of Carl Schmitt |
Authors | Michiel Besters |
Author's information |
Book Review |
Patrick Loobuyck, De seculiere samenleving. Over religie, atheïsme en democratie |
Authors | Stefan Rummens |
Author's information |